The Most General Factive Mental State Operator
Last week I re-read the first chapter of Timothy Williamson's Knowledge and Its Limits. TW argues that 'knows' is the most general factive mental state operator. To be a factive mental state operator (FMSO) is to be a factive semantically unanalyzable expression that attributes a propositional attitude to a subject. The semantic unanalyzability claim is that, by definition, an FMSO is never synonymous with a complex expression whose meaning is composed of the meanings of its parts. So, for instance, 'could hear' is a FMSO. There is a reading of it such that the presumption of truth is not cancelable, as is revealed by the deviance of
(1) She could hear that the volcano was erupting, but it was not erupting.
Moreover, the meaning of 'could hear' is not composed of the meanings of 'could' and 'hear', for that would assimilate 'could hear' to something like 'it is merely possible that s heard that p', which is not factive.
Additionally, 'could hear' is further evidence that 'knows' is the most general FMSO, since 's could hear that p' implies 's knows that p'.
Let's explore the properties of other FMSOs. I want to argue that there is a more general FMSO than 'knows'.
Consider the ambiguity in each of the following expressions:
'could see that'
'could hear that'
'could feel that',
'can't believe that'
'is not happy that'
'is not surprised that'
'failed to realize that'
'is not impressed that'
'is not able to taste that'
Each of these has a factive and a non-factive reading. For instance, 'cannot believe' is factive in
(2) I cannot believe that you are smoking again,
but is not factive in
(3) I cannot believe that I don't have any beliefs.
Now the non-factive readings of the above list items are semantically decomposable. They may be paraphrased roughly as
'it is false that s believes/is happy/is surprised/realizes/is impressed/is able to taste that'
or
'it is (merely) possible that the subject s sees/hears/feels that'.
Exactly analogous remarks may be made about knowability- and ignorance-attributions. More carefully, 'could have known that' and 'does not know that' both have a factive and a non-factive reading. Let's discuss 'could have known that'. The non-factive reading, perhaps not common in ordinary English, is that it is merely possible that s knows that p. The other reading carries a presumption of truth as in 's was in a position to know that p'. Notice that the presumption of truth is not cancelable. This is demonstrated by the deviance of the following claims:
(4) Andy could have known that grandmother was ill, even though she was not ill.
and
(5) Sally was in a position to know that Andy was cheating, but he was not cheating.
The deviance of the claims suggests that the presumption of truth is semantic and not cancelable.
As with the factive readings of the items on the above list, we should expect that the factive readings of 'could have known that' and 'is not known that' are not analyzable. My hypothesis is that they are not analyzable. And I suggest that the burden is on one who thinks otherwise to show that 'could have known' is different from all of our other factive operators of the form 'could have ___ed'.
Incidentally, the non-factive readings of all of the aforementioned expressions fail to attribute a propositional attitude to a subject. They either outright deny the presence of the attitude or affirm merely its possibility of obtaining. The factive readings of the above operators, on the other hand, all attribute a propositional attitude to a subject (with the exception of 'does not know that').
According to Williamson, when a propositional attitude that p is attributed, so is a grasp of the concepts in p. Since the factive reading of 'does not know' fails to attribute grasp of meaning, we may conclude that it is not a mental state operator. A fortiori it is not an FMSO. Importantly, 'could have known' does attribute grasp of meaning. Consider,
(6) Andy doesn't understand high-energy physics, yet he could have known that there are top quarks in pp collisions.
Or
(7) Andy doesn't grasp any of the rules of Chess. He was nevertheless in a position to know that his King was about to be mated.
The oddities of (6) and (7) suggest that knowability is a mental state---that 'to s it is knowable that p' implies 's has an attitude that p'---minimally, it implies 's grasps the meaning that p'. Similar things can be said about 's failed to realize that p'. It wouldn't be a failure to realize that p, if the subject didn't have a grasp of the concepts in p.
It would seem then that 'knowable' or 'could have known' is an FMSO. The problem for Williamson's account is that 's could have known that p' does not entail 's knows that p'. Hence, 'knows' is not the most general FMSO. Instead, the entailment goes the other way. Are we to conclude that 'could have known' is the most general FMSO?